




版權說明:本文檔由用戶提供并上傳,收益歸屬內容提供方,若內容存在侵權,請進行舉報或認領
文檔簡介
1、Carl Schmitts Two Concepts of HumanityMatthias LievensCatholic University of BrusselsVrijheidslaan 171081 BrusselsBelgiummatthias.lievenskubrussel.ac.beTel. + 32 2 412.42.76Fax. + 32 2 412.42.00Abstract: A dominant interpretation of Carl Schmitts work depicts him as a theologically inspired and anti
2、-humanist thinker. This paper argues, however, that his concept of the political, founded on a plea for relative instead of absolute enmity, takes Schmitt away from theology onto a profane level, where enemies recognize each other as human beings. Although Schmitt states that he who uses the concept
3、 of humanity wants to betray, one can trace in his work a distinction between two concepts of humanity which gives a philosophical foundation for the distinction between relative and absolute enmity, and thus, for the political. It is at the basis of a minimally normative understanding of the politi
4、cal which can be of great interest for contemporary debates on the contemporary world order. Key words: Carl Schmitt, the political, political theology, sovereignty, recognition, humanity, enmityIntroductionSchmitt is often depicted as a theologically inspired and anti-humanist thinker. A large numb
5、er of recent Schmitt readings underline the theological underpinnings of his writings. Moreover, he wrote two books titled Political Theology and is well-known as a fighting catholic.However, Schmitts philosophy is not as clear-cut as it may seem. In this article, I will argue against the dominant t
6、heological reading of Schmitt Cf. Heinrich Meier, Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss. The hidden dialogue(Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 1995); Heinrich Meier, The lesson of Carl Schmitt. Four Chapters on the Distinction between Political Theology and Political Philosophy (Chicago an
7、d London: The University of Chicago Press, 1998); Günter Meuter, Der Katechon. Zu Carl Schmitts fundamentalistischer Kritik der Zeit (Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 1994); Theo De Wit, De onontkoombaarheid van de politiek. De soevereine vijand in de politieke filosofie van Carl Schmitt (Ubergen
8、: Pomppers, 1992); Wolfgang Palaver. Die mythische Quellen des Politischen. Carl Schmitts Freund-Feind-Theorie (Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1998). to show that his concept of the political contains a profane and even humanist twist, which can also be used to deconstruct some of the more problematic parts
9、 of his work. Schmitts concept of the political entails a peculiar form of normativity and is based on a specific concept of humanity that he wants to rescue from the dominance of moral thinking in politicis in a liberal world. However odd that may seem, I will try to show that there is indeed a pol
10、itics of humanity present in Schmitts work, despite his severe criticisms of the use of the concept of humanity. The stake of elaborating upon this element in Schmitt is this. As we entered an era of global civil war, the frontiers between states no longer function as means to relativize enmity: str
11、uggle became deterritorialized. Frontiers and territoriality are becoming less and less factors that make the political possible. The search for the sources of the political and the avoidance of absolute enmity has to be oriented elsewhere. My hypothesis is that the analysis of Schmitts two concepts
12、 of humanity supplies important clues for such an endeavour. Current wars and trials in the name of humanity are rightly what Schmitt feared the most. He depicted these as the outcome of the logic of global civil war. But as I will try to show, there is an alternative way to conceive of the rescuing
13、 of the political without having to reterritorialize conflict. It is situated in the functioning of a specific concept of humanity within the symbolic order. In this sense, Schmitt does more than just unmasking the ideology of humanity, but he gives us clues for a more positive elaboration. That is
14、why thinking creatively with Schmitt can contribute to the current debate in political philosophy, to the extent that this engagement with Schmitt is, as Andreas Kalyvas states, “neither apologetic, nor dismissive, but reconstructive and selective.” Andreas Kalyvas, Whos afraid of Carl Schmitt, Phil
15、osophy and social Criticism 25, (1999): 89. The dialectic of the concept of humanitySchmitt is well-known as a critique of liberalism. Fundamentally, he claims, liberalism is internally contradictory to the extent that it lacks a necessary concept of the political (which Schmitt understands as based
16、 on the distinction between friends and enemies). Liberalism is an antipolitics, it is a theory which starts from an opposition to the state and the political, giving free space to ethics and economy instead Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996), p.
17、70. Political struggle dissolves in liberal theory into competition on the economic terrain, and discussion on the spiritual level.In practice, however, liberals of all countries have acted politically Ibid., p. 69. They formed coalitions and waged struggles, without recognizing the importance of th
18、e political as such. One cannot install a liberal order without a precedent process of political struggles and decisions. The crux of Schmitts critique of liberalism consists in his contention that when liberalism, with its stress on the “ideological humanitarian conception of humanity” Ibid., p. 72
19、., starts to act politically, it risks to turn this very idea into its opposite. When one makes an appeal to humanity, one has to give a qualitative content to this idea, drawing a distinction between what is really human and what isnt. In The Nomos of the Earth, Schmitt explains how humanists and h
20、umanitarians as Francis Bacon came to very inhuman conclusions in their dealings with indigenous peoples in newly colonized territories on the other side of the Atlantic. According to Bacon, these peoples were cannibals by nature, they were outside humanity and thus could not be seen to have rights.
21、 “By no means is it paradoxical,” Schmitt says, “that non other than humanists and humanitarians put forward such inhuman arguments, because the idea of humanity is two-sided and often lends itself to a surprising dialectic.” Carl Schmitt, The Nomos of the Earth in the International Law of the Jus P
22、ublicum Europaeum (New York: Telos Press Ltd., 2003), p. 103.A political struggle, waged in the name of humanity, tends to turn into the most intensive and extreme forms of struggle, where the enemy falls outside humanity. She is no longer recognized as a political opponent, but becomes criminalized
23、, outlawed. Liberal politics, too, slides very easily back into police actions, with its typical asymmetry between friend and enemy, as is the case in wars against terrorism and in the name of humanity, democracy or freedom, or in tribunals judging crimes against humanity. Such practices often even
24、go further than just criminalizing the enemy: in regular penal law, a criminal has certain rights of defence, while in extreme war situations, the enemy turned into a war criminal often even lacks these basic rights when he appears before exceptional courts.Drawing on these extreme situations, Schmi
25、tt tries to point to the impossibility of liberalism: it needs a politics, but doesnt or cant think it. And when it develops a politics in actual facts, this threatens to become an inhuman one. The (im)moralization of the enemy potentially leads to the most intensive forms of war which simply aims t
26、o annihilate the enemy. Liberalism is thus unable to provide a coherent theory. This doesnt mean Schmitt dismisses all its intuitions as such In some of his texts, Schmitt argues in favour of human rights, freedom of thought, the rule of law, property rights etc. (e.g. Carl Schmitt, Verfassungsrecht
27、liche Aufsätze aus den Jahren 1924-1954. Materialen zu einer Verfassungslehre (Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 1985), p. 230; cf. Reinhard Merhing, Der Begriff des politischen. Ein kooperativer Kommentar (Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 2003), p. 81). But its starting point is wrong. When one starts fr
28、om a moral theory of the human and its values, which claims universal validity, it becomes impossible to formulate a theory of the political. Schmitt begins the other way round: he starts with the concept of the political, in order to render it more human.Taking Schmitt away from theologyParadoxical
29、ly, the attempt to find a human form of the political seems to take Schmitt into a very profane direction. Schmitts concept of the political is based on the famous criterion of the distinction between friend and enemy. “The distinction of friend and enemy denotes the utmost degree of intensity of a
30、union or separation, of an association or dissociation” Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, p. 26. In fact, he locates the political on a scale of increasing intensity, ranging from a pre-political level, where the social relation is not interpreted in terms of friend/enemy oppositions, goin
31、g via an actual political level, to a hyperpolitical level where the conflict is intensified to such a degree that the enemy becomes moralised Carl Schmitt, Glossarium: Aufzeichnungen der Jahre 1947-1951 (Berlin: Duncker und Humblot, 1991), p. 190; Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, p. 36;
32、Carl Schmitt, Theory of the partisan, in: CR: The New Centennial Review 4, 3 (2004): 67. or theologised Carl Schmitt, Ex captivitate salus. Erfahrungen der Zeit 1945/47 (Berlin : Duncker & Humblot, 2002), p. 89 Carl Schmitt, Theory of the Partisan, p. 66 Carl Schmitt, Glossarium
33、, p. 190; Jakob Taubes, En divergent accord. A propos de Carl Schmitt (Paris : Payot et Rivages, 2003), p. 25. This last situation is dangerous, according to Schmitt, because such a struggle, which tends to strip the enemy off his human character, potentially opens the door for a war of annihil
34、ation. “Such a war is necessarily unusually intense and inhuman because, by transcending the limits of the political framework, it simultaneously degrades the enemy into moral and other categories and is forced to make of him a monster that must not only be defeated but also utterly destroyed.” Carl
35、 Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, p. 36. The rigorous consequence of a confrontation with an immoral enemy is the decision to totally annihilate her. The theologisation of the enemy has a similar effect of intensifying the conflict to an inhuman degree Schmitt sees also the opposite movement:
36、a conflict which leads to the annihilation of the enemy, theologises him. “He who wants to annihilate me, is not my enemy, but my satanic prosecutor”. Carl Schmitt, Glossarium, p. 190. Schmitts theory of the political is thus aimed at finding a middle ground, recognizing the reality of political con
37、flict, and at the same time avoiding its degeneration into a war of annihilation.As said, a great part of the secondary literature on Schmitt deals with the theological or even mythical underpinnings of his writings. It was Heinrich Meier who inaugurated the theological turn in the literature on Sch
38、mitt. This could only be done by downplaying the distinction Schmitt draws between the political and what transcends the limits of the political framework, i.e. between the genuinely political enemy (the relative enemy) and the moralised or theologised, and thus absolute, enemy This essential distin
39、ction is pictured by the editors of Telos as the distinction between enemy and foe. See the special issue of Telos on Carl Schmitt, 72 (1987). Meier never speaks of relative enmity in the first place, and claims that “Schmitts later differentiation between the conventional, the real, and the absolut
40、e enemy () is not decisive for the concept of the political.” Heinrich Meier, Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss. The hidden dialogue(Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1995), p. 26. Our contention, however, is that Schmitts theory necessitates a clear delineation of the genuinely political,
41、 characterised by relative enmity and based on a specific concept of humanity, and that this concept of the political leads into a profane direction Heinrich Meier also omits two crucial features of the political in Schmitts view, notably the collective and public character of political conflicts. S
42、ee Jan-Werner Müller, A Dangerous Mind. Carl Schmitt in Post-War European Thought (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2003), p. 204. This distinction between relative and absolute enmity is a key to make sense of Schmitts work I do not agree on this regard with Ernesto Laclau when he argues that
43、 “the distinction between real ad absolute enemy is secondary only a matter of degree” (Ernesto Laclau, On Real and Absolute Enemies, in: CR: The New Centennial Review 5, 1 (2005): 11). What defines absolute enemy is a specific, exclusive concept of humanity. The examples of real enmity that Schmitt
44、 gives, lack a foundation in such a concept. . This development onto a profane level takes place through two successive moves. Firstly, Schmitt states that all political concepts are secularised theological concepts Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, p. 36. This doesnt make Schmitt a theolo
45、gian, however. In Political Theology, he says of political theories that they cannot be understood without understanding their historical origin in theology and their structural similarity to theological conceptions. He sees for instance an analogy between deism and the scientific way of thinking of
46、 the Enlightenment Carl Schmitt, Political Theology. Four chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1988), p. 48. Still, this must not be read too strictly: Schmitt would never agree with the political counterpart of theism, notably world monarchy Cf. Wolfgang Palaver, Die mythis
47、che Quellen des Politischen. Carl Schmitts Freund-Feind-Theorie (Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1998), p. 21. The political concepts with which Schmitt is dealing (e.g. the State and Sovereignty), thus have a certain independence vis-à-vis their theological origins. Time and again, Schmitt cites Alberi
48、cus Gentilis phrase “Silete theologi in munere alieno!” Cf. Carl Schmitt, Ex Captivitate Salus, p. 70 Carl Schmitt, The Nomos of the Earth, p. 126. This must be read as also applying to Schmitt himself.What political concepts do retain from their theological origins, however, is something of t
49、heir absolute character. Indeed, in Political Romanticism, Schmitt conceives secularisation as the process through which the absolute shifts from one instance to another: for instance, from God to “mundane and worldly factors” Carl Schmitt, Political Romanticism (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1986), pp. 17-
50、18. In this sense, political concepts such as the State and Sovereignty are still somehow imbued with the absolute character they inherited from their theological origins. In a second move, then, Schmitt implicitly takes a step further away from the theological origins of political concepts through
51、his defence of the political as defined in terms of relative instead of absolute enmity. The absolute enemy is the one who simply has to be annihilated because he is inhuman, immoral or an obstacle for the course of History. Relative enmity presupposes a certain respect for the human and political d
52、ignity of the adversary, as I will show in the development of the concept below. What is important at this stage, is that while secularisation remained somehow within a religious frame of thought, focusing on notions of the absolute (no longer a strictly theological absolute, but the absolute of the
53、 State, Sovereignty, Morality, History or Humanity with a majuscule), Schmitts concept of the political, defined in terms of relative enmity, now leaves this frame behind in favour of a relativisation of such absolute concepts. This takes him - maybe unwittingly - to a very profane level, where the
54、political in Schmitts sense can be found: it discards all absolute truths and instances in the name of which struggles are waged, and opens a space for relativity and openness. It is this level that Schmitt wants to rescue from absolute notions that lurk behind the criminalization of the enemy in a
55、certain liberal moralism or in the Marxist tendency to see the class enemy as a relic of a society that is doomed by the course of History. Such a relativisation of enmity represents for Schmitt “a great progress from a humane point of view” Carl Schmitt, Het Begrip Politiek (Amsterdam: Boom, 2001),
56、 p. 48., as it goes against the “moral and physical annihilation of the enemy”.Although Schmitt has very often been criticized as war-prone, the acknowledgement of the proper level of the political as the terrain of relative enmity is the precondition to avoid absolute wars and regulate the conflict
57、 in the real world of politics. The paradox Schmitt underlines is that no morality can legitimise the killing of other people Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, p. 49., while at the same time the moralisation of politics, for instance through the concept of humanity, leads very fast to the
58、conclusion that the enemy has to be annihilated and thus intensifies the conflict beyond the proper political level. Instead of being bellicose, Schmitts concept of the political has the ambition to defer the moment of taking resort to violence, and to avoid the rapid intensification of the conflict
59、 into a war of annihilation Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, p. 35. Schmitts relativisation of enmity thus claims to lead to less violence. He underlines the way absolute ideas function ideologically to intensify the struggle and accelerate the use of violence: “As Trotsky justly reminded the democrat Kautsky, the awareness of relative truths never gives one the courage to use force and to spill blood.” Carl Schmitt, The crisis of p
溫馨提示
- 1. 本站所有資源如無特殊說明,都需要本地電腦安裝OFFICE2007和PDF閱讀器。圖紙軟件為CAD,CAXA,PROE,UG,SolidWorks等.壓縮文件請下載最新的WinRAR軟件解壓。
- 2. 本站的文檔不包含任何第三方提供的附件圖紙等,如果需要附件,請聯系上傳者。文件的所有權益歸上傳用戶所有。
- 3. 本站RAR壓縮包中若帶圖紙,網頁內容里面會有圖紙預覽,若沒有圖紙預覽就沒有圖紙。
- 4. 未經權益所有人同意不得將文件中的內容挪作商業或盈利用途。
- 5. 人人文庫網僅提供信息存儲空間,僅對用戶上傳內容的表現方式做保護處理,對用戶上傳分享的文檔內容本身不做任何修改或編輯,并不能對任何下載內容負責。
- 6. 下載文件中如有侵權或不適當內容,請與我們聯系,我們立即糾正。
- 7. 本站不保證下載資源的準確性、安全性和完整性, 同時也不承擔用戶因使用這些下載資源對自己和他人造成任何形式的傷害或損失。
最新文檔
- 學習數據庫環境中的有效評估方法試題及答案
- 數據庫模塊化設計的優勢分析試題及答案
- 小學鼓樂教室管理制度
- 大地影院資金管理制度
- 學校桌椅使用管理制度
- 廣播電視設備管理制度
- 員工違反公司管理制度
- 外協車輛使用管理制度
- 小學課堂分組管理制度
- 小學陽光課間管理制度
- (完整)開發區土地集約利用評價規程(2014年度試行)(文檔良心出品)
- 電解質第九講(偶極子轉向極化)
- 綜合辦公室安全職責
- 初中畢業證書怎么查詢電子版
- 事業單位工作人員年度考核登記表
- 遠程培訓學習總結(4篇)
- 全息照相與信息光學實驗報告
- 2022年02月上海鐵路局下屬鐵路疾病預防控制所公開招聘畢業生筆試參考題庫含答案解析
- YY/T 1293.4-2016接觸性創面敷料第4部分:水膠體敷料
- 激光設備買賣合同模板(2篇)
- GB/T 24815-2009起重用短環鏈吊鏈等用6級普通精度鏈
評論
0/150
提交評論